Perspectives
Print
Perspectives
Natural reward drives the advancement of life
expand article infoOwen M. Gilbert
‡ University of Texas at Austin, Austin, United States of America
Open Access

Abstract

Throughout the history of life on earth, rare and complex innovations have periodically increased the efficiency with which abiotic free energy and biotic resources are converted to biomass and organismal diversity. Such macroevolutionary expansions have increased the total amount of abiotic free energy utilized by life and shaped the earth’s ecosystems. Meanwhile, Darwin’s theory of natural selection assumes a historical, worldwide state of effective resource limitation, which could not possibly be true if life evolved from one or a few original ancestors. In this paper, I analyze the self-contradiction in Darwin’s theory that comes from viewing the world and universe as effectively resource limited. I then extend evolutionary theory to include a second deterministic evolutionary force, natural reward. Natural reward operates on complex inventions produced by natural selection and is analogous to the reward for innovation in human economic systems. I hypothesize that natural reward, when combined with climate change and extinction, leads to the increased innovativeness, or what I call the advancement, of life with time. I then discuss applications of the theory of natural reward to the evolution of evolvability, the apparent sudden appearance of new forms in the fossil record, and human economic evolution. I conclude that the theory of natural reward holds promise as an explanation for the historical advancement of life on earth.

Keywords

invention, entrepreneurship, innovation, success, progress, advancement

Introduction

Charles Darwin, in "The Origin of Species", derived a radical new theory using an analogy between artificial selection and a hypothetical force of nature that he called natural selection (Darwin 1859). Darwin’s analogy has proven so powerful in understanding evolutionary change that scientists now speak of natural selection as if it is a true force of nature, rather than a concept that Darwin created. Yet, Darwin uniquely developed the metaphor of natural selection, departed from the normal scientific methods by devising a rash new framework, and revolutionized the way that facts were taken to support a theory.

After over 150 years of development, Darwin’s theory has now fulfilled the destiny that Huxley (1880), p. 549 anticipated. Starting as heresy, it has now become a doctrine that is accepted with as little reflection as Darwin’s contemporaries once rejected it. The main doctrine that is uncritically accepted is that natural selection is the only non-random, lawlike (deterministic) force of evolution, and is complemented only by random forces-like mutation, recombination, and genetic drift (Simpson 1944, 1949, 1953; Dobzhansky 1951; Stebbins 1959).

In our modern world of rapid human technological evolution, we are now positioned to ask whether Darwin’s theory might be extended fruitfully to cover deep evolutionary time. Recently, human technological evolution has revealed themes that occur millions of times faster in human culture compared to organic evolution. There is a parallel, for example, between the large-scale expansion of human economies and terrestrial ecological diversity (Fig. 1). The rate at which whole new technologies originate, spread, and go obsolete is known to anyone who owns a computer or smartphone.

Figure 1.

Expansion in A human economies, as represented by world gross domestic product (GDP), measured as the total monetary or market value of all the finished goods and services produced, and population B nature, as measured by the number of terrestrial animal species A redrawn from ourworldindata.org B redrawn from Benton (2016).

In this paper, I outline a theory of evolution based on a metaphorical link between the reward for innovation in human societies and a force of nature that I call natural reward. I adopt Darwin’s approach of inventing a new theory, and then asking how it illuminates various classes of phenomena. I will begin by explaining how a self-contradiction in Darwin’s theory created a schizophrenic state of modern evolutionary theory. I will then show how a proper understanding of Darwin’s theory allows us to break free of the delusions and abnormal interpretations of reality that come from the uncritical acceptance of both of Darwin’s conflicting messages. I finally outline a new theory, based on an alternative deterministic force of evolution, natural reward, which I propose acts synergistically with natural selection.

The Darwinian double bind

A double bind is a dilemma in communication in which an individual or group receives two or more conflicting messages from an authority, which the receiver cannot resolve or opt out of (Bateson et al. 1956). Bateson et al. (1956) argued that double binds imposed on children can lead to the development of schizophrenia, a mental disorder characterized by abnormal interpretations of reality, disorganized thinking, and delusions. I argue that Darwin, by giving conflicting messages, created a double bind for modern evolutionists.

Darwin’s double bind manifests as the conflicting messages that: (i) natural selection yields comparative progress only, and (ii) natural selection also yields absolute progress (Box 1). The authors of the modern synthesis could not comment on the contradiction without revealing a weak point of evolutionary theory to political and religion-based ideological opponents, who promoted the teaching of pseudoscience in high school classrooms (Tax and Callender 1960b; p. 42). Therefore, the authors of the modern synthesis accepted both messages as correct, and thus in fighting pseudoscience, advocated a theory that contradicted itself (e.g., Simpson 1949, p. 269; Dobzhansky 1951, p. 17; Stebbins 1959, pp. 305–306). Evolutionists since that time have accepted both contradictory messages in various ways (Ruse 1993, 1996), in some cases apparently unaware of the contradiction. This led to a schizophrenic state of modern evolutionary theory.

Box 1.

The Darwinian Self-Contradiction.

Ruse (1993), p. 58 pointed out that Darwin tried to get absolute progress from comparative progress, where comparative progress involves the adaptive advance of one line of organisms over others, and absolute progress involves improvement on a scale of fixed value. In our modern understanding of evolution, comparative progress refers to the adaptive replacement of one allele by another. For example, an allele for non-cooperation might replace an allele for cooperation in an environment characterized by frequent associations with non-relatives (Gilbert et al. 2007). An allele for non-cooperation may thus be progressive with respect to the immediate social environment, but may lead to extinction (e.g., Fiegna and Velicer 2003). Whether natural selection leads to continued population survival or extinction may depend on the arbitrary state of the environment (Travisano et al. 2018; Svensson and Connallon 2019).
With respect to comparative progress, Darwin stressed that natural selection acts only by the accumulation of slight modifications of structure or instinct, each profitable to the individual under its conditions of life (Darwin 1859, pp. 170, 233, 235, 435), that natural selection produces only relative perfection and that true wonder is why imperfection is not more commonly observed (Darwin 1859, p. 472), and that natural selection, though sometimes leading to advancement, includes no necessary law of advancement – and could just as easily lead to retrogression (Darwin 1859, p. 133, 137). With respect to absolute progress, on the other hand, Darwin argued that species going extinct would tend to have an inferiority held in common (Darwin 1859, pp. 321–322, 327, 344), that those rising to dominance would have a superiority held in common (p. 128), and that natural selection causes newer forms to supplant their less-improved ancestors (pp. 5, 108, 119, 126–128, 337).
In an 1854 letter to Hooker, Darwin said, “With respect to ‘highness’ & ‘lowness,’ my ideas are only eclectic & not very clear” (Darwin-Hooker 27 Jun 1854). Nevertheless, throughout his works, Darwin never commented on the inconsistency between absolute perfection and relative perfection. Instead, in later editions of The Origin, Darwin argued that the “improvement” caused by natural selection, “inevitably leads to the gradual advancement of the organization of the greater number of living beings throughout the world” (Darwin 1876, p. 97).

This schizophrenia is characterized by the metaphysical delusion of teleology. Teleology is the doctrine that final causes exist, and that the study of apparent design in nature provides evidence for final causes. Today in evolutionary theory, teleological research programs explain the existence or ubiquity of complex traits by appeal to final causes. They do so by a sequence of habits. The first habit is to take the apparent design function of a trait as the cause for its existence. I call this invoking a design-function final cause. The second habit is to causally link the design function to the cause for existence by a general principle, like “fitness maximization” (Ayala 1970; Grafen 2014). I refer to this habit as invoking a unifying final cause. The third habit is to take apparent design in nature as evidence of a unifying final cause, and by implication, a design-function final cause. I call this habit teleological empiricism.

An example of these habits culminating in teleological empiricism comes from the study of kin recognition. Here, the first habit is to assume that kin recognition evolves for the apparent design function of directing help to kin (Grafen 1990). The second habit is to link the design function to the cause for existence by the unifying final cause of inclusive fitness maximization (West and Gardner 2013; Grafen 2014). The third habit is to take apparent design of kin recognition in nature as evidence for the unifying final cause (Fletcher and Michener 1987, p. 419), and by implication, the design-function final cause.

The result of the persistence of teleological thinking in prominent fields of evolutionary biology is that the current climate is much like it was immediately after the publication of "The Origin of Species". In that era, researchers disagreed about whether Darwin had supported or replaced teleology (Huxley 1870, p. 330). Likewise, evolutionists today still debate how Darwin’s theory relates to teleology (Ayala 1970; Ghiselin 1994; Huneman 2019). I therefore will close the door to teleological interpretations of natural selection by first explaining the importance of the struggle-for-existence metaphor for Darwin’s theory.

The struggle for existence

Evolutionists since Darwin have relied on the foundations that Darwin provided with the struggle for existence metaphor, without understanding its importance. Fisher (1953), p. 5 argued that Darwin’s notion of the struggle for existence was a “journalistic slogan” that Darwin used to get his doctrine across to a “thick-headed audience.” Dobzhansky (1951), p. 77 asserted that Darwin’s metaphors were “more picturesque than accurate,” and Lewontin (1970), p. 1 that the idea of competition for resources in short supply was “not integral” to Darwin’s argument. Textbooks today teach the conditions for natural selection with no mention of the struggle for existence or resource limitation (e.g., Freeman and Herron 2007, pp. 76–77; Barton et al. 2007, pp. 458, 460, 474; Bergstrom and Dugatkin 2011, p. 63–64). I therefore will first review the importance of Darwin’s struggle for existence metaphor for his theory. I will then disprove Lewontin’s (1970) arguments against it.

To begin with, the struggle for existence metaphor determined how Darwin applied his theory to comparative progress. In adopting Malthus’s doctrine and applying it to nature, Darwin derived two arguments. First, Darwin suggested that the world was already resource limited (Fig. 2A). Darwin (1859), p. 67 captured his worldview by stating, “The face of Nature may be compared to a yielding surface, with ten thousand sharp wedges packed close together and driven inwards by incessant blows…” Therefore, “… from the high geometrical powers of increase of all organic beings, each area is already fully stocked with inhabitants, it follows that as each selected and favoured form increases in number, so will the less favoured forms decrease and become rare” (p. 109). Thus, the world is already packed with wedges, and the placement of a new wedge (species) requires either tighter wedging, or that a wedge is thrust out by extinction (Stauffer 1975, pp. 208, 631).

Figure 2.

Different perspectives on the world resource supply. A Darwin’s first argument assumes population have hit the ultimate limit of food supply. The placement of a new wedge (species) requires that another be thrust out by extinction. B Darwin’s second argument assumes that the ultimate check of limited food is not reached because of various other checks to increase. C Malthus assumed that populations are continually in a state of effective resource limitation even though the food supply is increasing, because linear increases of food are quickly exhausted by the exponential population increases that they cause. D There is an unlimited abiotic resource supply, and the biotic “food supply” is increasing by innovations in primary production.

In some other passages, however, Darwin reasoned that unrestricted increase would lead to the earth being covered by the progeny of a single pair of organisms, however slow breeding (Darwin 1859, p. 64). In that case, climatic variability (p. 68), climatic extremes (p. 69), microbial epidemics (p. 70), or parasitic insects (p. 72), prevent the ultimate check of limited food (p. 68; Fig. 2B). Darwin (p. 74) thus suggested that for any given species, “…many different checks, acting at different periods of life, and during different seasons or years, probably come into play…”

In either case, Darwin used his assumption of effective resource limitation to define the form of competition. Darwin argued that the struggle for existence is most severe among those competing for the same resources (Darwin 1859, pp. 68, 75, 76, 121, 320, 468), and identified the species as the set of individuals closely resembling each other (pp. 52, 481), which are discrete compared to other sets (p. 482). Darwin then reasoned that evolution by natural selection is a within-species process, because only types within species are near enough in their resource requirements to competitively displace each other (pp. 4, 5, 75–76, 80–130; see also Fisher 1930, p. 121). Darwin also reasoned that because members of the same species are similar in their resource requirements, their variations would be slight (Darwin 1859, pp. 81–86), and modifications of form and function gradual (Darwin 1859, pp. 186–190, 233–235; see also Fisher 1930, pp. 38–41).

Lewontin (1970), in contrast, proposed that the only condition for natural selection is heritable variation in fitness, with fitness defined as net reproductive success (sensu Fisher 1930, p. 34). Lewontin did not include the struggle for existence in his conditions for natural selection, and this omission meant that it was no longer clear that natural selection applies only within species. Instead, it seemed that natural selection might apply to any level with heritable variation in “fitness” (e.g., possibly species, phyla, and ecological communities; Lewontin 1970). Therefore, it is important to examine Lewontin’s argument for why the struggle for existence can be ignored. Lewontin’s first argument is that resource limitation is unnecessary for organisms to struggle for existence because, as Darwin argued, factors other than limited food (e.g., limited water, parasites, predators) might check populations (see above). A plant on the edge of the desert may be said to struggle against the drought because in that case, moisture limitation rather than food limitation provides the main check to population increase (Lewontin 1970, p. 1; Darwin 1859, p. 62). However, Darwin (1859) assumed an “extreme limit” of a fixed food supply (p. 68), whether or not the population was actually checked by food limitation (Fig. 2A, B) or other factors (Fig. 2B). Therefore, Lewontin overlooked the importance of the extreme limit of food in Darwin’s argument, which then caused Lewontin to dismiss the importance of the struggle for existence.

Lewontin’s second argument examines the extreme situation in which not even food checks a population. Here, Lewontin argued that if two bacterial strains are growing exponentially in an excess of nutrients and one strain grows faster than the other, then natural selection has happened between the different strains. Lewontin took this to suggest that natural selection would happen even without checks to increase, thus apparently disproving the importance of the struggle for existence in defining the levels of selection. However, Lewontin’s argument can be scrutinized by taking the thought experiment to its logical extreme. If the strains continued to grow in an abundance of nutrients indefinitely, neither strain would ever displace the other. Without any competitive displacement of types, it is unclear how evolution by natural selection could happen. If food became limited, moreover, natural selection would not necessarily act between the strains. If the strains use the same resources differently, or depend on different resources (e.g., one feeds off the metabolic byproduct of the other; Blount 2017), they may persist indefinitely as separate species. In that case, the different strains would evolve by natural selection separately, because the struggle for existence would happen only within a strain. In other words, the struggle for existence would still determine the levels at which natural selection acts, just as Darwin argued.

Thus, Darwin’s reasoning from the struggle for existence justified his application of natural selection to the gradual adaptation of species to their immediate environments and thus to comparative progress (Box 1). Reasoning from the struggle for existence, there were only two ways that absolute progress could happen. Under Darwin’s first perspective (Fig. 2A), evolution over many thousands of generations may yield a tighter wedging. Thus, Darwin argued that a greater amount of life could be supported with a greater diversity of species (Darwin 1859, p. 114). Under Darwin’s second perspective (Fig. 2B), long-term evolution may yield an increase of population, for example if a release from alternative checks to increase allows the world population to come closer to the ultimate check of limited food. Yet, although Darwin sometimes referred to population increase (Darwin 1859, p. 102, 119, 472), he never discussed whether there was some greater untapped resource supply (Fig. 2C, D), as would be necessary for the expansion of all life on earth from one or a few original forms (Darwin 1859, p. 491).

The struggle for supremacy

In contrast to Darwin, Malthus (1826) explicitly allowed an increase in the food supply (Fig. 2C). However, Malthus considered human populations, and his assumption of increases of food supply was warranted by innovations in agriculture. If life had expanded from a few simple ancestors, however, life’s “food supply” must have increased. In this section, I will briefly review the basic ways that life’s food supply has increased and how this relates to an alternative struggle of life.

To begin with, early life used geothermal sources of energy and only later gained the ability to use solar power (Judson 2017). A major increase of the resource supply came when photosynthesis first originated in anoxygenic form, about 3.7 Gy (Judson 2017). Another major step came 2.45–2.32 Gy, with the origin of modern oxygenic photosynthesis, which uses the energy from light to split water and make glucose as food (Judson 2017). During the Jurassic and early Cretaceous 200–130 My, a reduction of genome and cell size in angiosperms allowed optimization of C3 photosynthesis (Simonin and Roddy 2018; Gago et al. 2020). Even in the past 1% of life’s history (40 million years), a reduction of atmospheric CO2 combined with increased aridity of certain regions provided an ecological opportunity for C4 photosynthesis (Edwards et al. 2010), which allowed plants to succeed in the modern atmosphere with lower CO2 (Sage et al. 2012). Such innovations at the base level of life’s food chain provided opportunities that facilitated further expansions of life.

Regarding the source of life’s food supply, we now know that it ultimately comes from fusion reactions in stars like our sun (Eddington 1920). Our sun emits 3.7 x 1026 W (Kaushika et al. 2018), less than a billionth of which (1.78 × 1017 W) strikes the earth’s outer atmosphere (Wald 2009). The sun is but one of a trillion stars in the Milky Way (Odenwald 2017), which is one of two trillion galaxies in the observable universe (Conselice et al. 2016). Just on earth, a full half of the incident solar radiation (8.9 × 1016 W) is not reflected back to space nor dissipated by hydrogeological cycles, but is dissipated as heat (Davis 1990). Photosynthetic organisms today use 0.14% of this available power (1.30 × 1014 W; Steger et al. 2005), and this constitutes the primary source of power source of life (Judson 2017). Even a seven-fold increase of life’s power usage would still leave 99% of that which is dissipated as heat to maintain global environmental temperatures. It seems likely, then, that life has not fully exploited the sun’s power, even within the confines of maintaining the earth’s life-supporting balance.

Based on these facts, I allow an alternative scheme, where there is an unlimited external energy source (Fig. 2D). The biotic “food supply” then increases by innovations in primary production. These innovations convert the abiotic free energy into biotic resources, which provide food for higher trophic levels. The consequence of an abundant abiotic resource supply is therefore a recurrent release from checks to increase, or what I call the struggle for supremacy.

The struggle for supremacy is a temporary phenomenon that manifests when populations escape the struggle for existence. Though infrequent, transient population increases can have major impacts on evolution. A population of bacteria that doubles once every thousand years will, in 100,000 years, either exhaust its resource supply or include more than 2100 ≈ 1030 members, which is about equal to the number of all bacteria on earth (Wasik and Turner 2013, p. 521).

All of the advances in photosynthesis cited above involved the primary level of the food chain. Other traits may, however, increase primary production by ecological feedback loops. For example, in the world’s oceans most of the biomass is heterotrophic (Bar-On et al. 2019), and primary-producing phytoplankton are limited by light and nutrients available in the photic zone (Sigman and Hain 2012). Heterotrophic decomposition of phytoplankton biomass drives nutrient cycling, which in turn increases primary production (Sigman and Hain 2012). Likewise, in terrestrial environments, grazers decompose dead plant material, return nutrients to base layers, return CO2 to the atmosphere, and spread plant propagules. Evolutionary innovations that lead to additional trophic levels could thus increase primary production.

The potential for transient population increases at different trophic levels means that there is an alternative form of competition in long-term evolution. Here, the first form to exploit a resource opportunity expands in population, and diversifies into a clade of specialized species. Those who win the race to innovate gain an incumbent advantage (Rosenzweig and McCord 1991), which prevents others from radiating into the resource base (Simpson 1944, 1953; Benton 1987). Such an incumbent advantage could arise with the exploitation of an abiotic or biotic resource. If a strain of Pseudomonas fluorescens bacteria exploits the abundant nutrients provided in a laboratory environment, it will prevent the radiation of other strains (Brockhurst et al. 1997). If a plant is the first to invent an improved photosynthetic ability (Gago et al. 2020), it will win the race to innovate compared to other plants.

Factors that may trigger large-scale expansions include the novel invention of a new trait, the dispersal or movement into an unoccupied territory, or a change in climate or environment that favors an existing form that is pre-adapted to the new condition (Wright 1948; Simpson 1953; Losos 2011). The clearance of an entire zone by a natural disaster or climate change can also provide the conditions within which novel invention, preadaptation, dispersal, and further changes of environment contribute to expansion (Lidgard et al. 1993; Benton 1996; Staubwasser et al. 2018). Under the struggle for existence, in contrast, an allele that spreads may exist for thousands of generations in a single functional form before being replaced by a slightly altered allele. There is no incumbent advantage of alleles diversifying into a set of specialized alleles as there is for species.

Darwin himself tended to view the competition between higher taxa in the same way as he viewed competition within species (Simpson 1944, p. 212; Benton 1987). When we allow for resource abundance and transient population increases, however, we also allow for a prominent role of indirect competition in macroevolution that happens as a race to innovate. This does not mean that higher taxa never directly replace each other. It simply means that such replacements, where they do occur, are an incidental consequence of a competition that occurred as a race to innovate.

Natural reward

The potential for transient population increase means that those organisms that are first to win the race to innovate are naturally rewarded with an incumbent advantage. This suggests the possibility of natural reward as a deterministic force of evolution separate from natural selection. How might we conceptualize this force, and what are its consequences?

To begin with, I use the term artificial reward to denote the supernormal profits earned by innovators in human economies (Prinsep and Biddle 1880, p. 84; Aghion and Howitt 2009, p. 7). As Aghion and Howwitt (2009), p. 7 describe it, “…the reward for innovation is monopoly profit, which comes from being able to do something that your rivals haven’t yet been able to match.” In this sense, the monopoly profit in human societies, which provides an artificial reward for innovation (Schumpeter 1942, p. 102), is analogous to the incumbent advantage in nature (Rosenzweig and McCord 1991), which provides a natural reward for innovation.

To separate the roles of natural selection and natural reward, I distinguish the roles of invention and entrepreneurship, known from studies of human innovation (Schumpeter 1942, p. 132; Schumpeter 1947, p. 152). In human technological evolution, invention refers to the initial origin or creation of technological novelties (Paley 2010; Grossman 2011). The process of entrepreneurship, in contrast, typically involves dissemination of inventions (Murphy 2015, pp. 70–71). For example, Steve Wozniak played the role of inventor, and Steve Jobs the role of entrepreneur in the early days of Apple Computer, because Wozniak created the first Apple computers, and Jobs spread them to markets (Wozniak 2007; Isaacson 2011). Likewise, authors often play the role of inventor and literary agents the role of entrepreneur in the origin and dissemination of literature. The entrepreneurial function is often overlooked because it does not consist of creating anything new (Schumpeter 1942, p. 132), but instead refers to the spread of inventions to new markets that demand them.

Emerging markets are often highly complex, chaotic and unpredictable based on past experiences. Therefore, the best entrepreneurial strategies are reactive rather than predictive (Christensen 1997, p. 129; Felin et al. 2014, p. 270), and many human inventions often originate through a process of conscious building combined with random error and succeed for unanticipated reasons (e.g., Wagner and Rosen 2013, p. 2). If nature operates similarly, then nature’s entrepreneur may operate without foresight.

If we allow natural selection to play the role of nature’s blind inventor (Jacob 1977; Dawkins 1986), and natural reward to play the role of nature’s blind entrepreneur, we are led to a theory of evolution that invokes only deterministic forces (Table 1 and Fig. 3). Under this theory, the dominant situation of nature is resource abundance (Fig. 3B). Transient population increases quickly lead to resource limitation and checks to increase (Fig. 3, top). The effective resource limitation leads to a struggle for existence, natural selection, and survival of optimized alleles. There are then two consequences of natural selection (Fig. 3A). First, over intermediate time scales of a thousand to a million generations, natural selection leads to the origin of inventions. Over broader time scales, and with climate change and extinction, natural selection leads to the origin of idiosyncratic traits that appear as one arbitrary thing after another (McShea and Simpson 2011; Fig. 3A).

Figure 3.

Comparison of theories of natural selection and natural reward. A The theory of natural selection includes A only. B The theory of natural reward includes A and B, and the connection between them.

Table 1.

Key concepts in relation to the deterministic forces.

Natural selection Natural reward
Universal energy abundance Irrelevant Relevant
Resource situation experienced by life Effective resource limitation Effective resource abundance
Resource use Use resources already in use Expansion to new resources
Struggle Struggle for existence Struggle for supremacy
Unit of competition Alleles within species Genetic systems shared by higher taxa (Table 2)
Typical outcome of competition Survival of the optimized alleles (“comparative progress”) Success of the innovative genetic systems
Long-term effects (103–106 generations) Origin of inventions through blind processes (nature’s “blind inventor”) Spread of inventions that tap new markets (nature’s “blind entrepreneur”), population expansion and diversification (“absolute progress”)
Extremely long-term effects (cycles of 103–106 generations) None Buildup of traits that facilitate further exploration and discovery of resource zones (“advancement”)

With natural reward, however, the recurrent potential for population increase also means that over broad time scales, populations also exist in a state of effective resource abundance (Fig. 3B). A state of effective resource abundance means a recurrent potential for transient population increases. These will favor those populations and genetic systems that are the first to exploit untapped resources. Here, acting as nature’s blind entrepreneur, natural reward spreads inventions to those biological markets that demand them (Fig. 3B). There are then two consequences of natural reward. During transient population expansions, natural reward spreads the traits that are gradually produced by natural selection. Over vast time frames, which include multiple rounds of invention and expansion (cycles of 103–106 generations), natural reward leads to the success of innovative forms of life, which are better able to explore and discover new resources.

The success of the innovative

In contrast to the case for natural selection, the progress produced by natural reward is absolute. Under natural selection, progress occurs as a change in allele frequency that optimizes each gene to its immediate situation. The adaptive progress is comparative in the sense that it pertains only to the immediate environment (Fig. 4A). In contrast, natural reward alters the total population size of a clade of organisms sharing a particular genetic system (Fig. 4B; here I use genetic system to mean heritable information encoded at any level of the genetic hierarchy; Table 2). As depicted in Fig. 4C, species A and B exploit a similar resource and are thus both potentially capable of exploiting a novel resource. Only species B expands to exploit the resource, and its large population size, and spread over potential physical and ecological isolating barriers, causes it to produce species C. The taxon including species B and C (blue) is then protected by an incumbent advantage of having a set of more diversified and specialized species. Therefore, the genetic system shared by species B and C wins the race to innovate compared to that of species A and is naturally rewarded with an incumbent advantage.

Figure 4.

Consequences of natural selection and natural reward. A Natural selection causes a change in allele frequencies, and consequently optimizes each gene to its immediate environment. B Natural reward causes a change in the total abundance of a genetic system. Here, species A does not exploit a new resource, which species B exploits. Species B expands in population and gives rise to species C, resulting in an increase in the total abundance of the genetic system ultimately shared by species B and C (blue). C Diagrams showing how species depicted in (B) track to resources. Speciation between species B and C begins with a cessation of gene flow. Species C then evolves differentially by natural selection to its new resource base.

Table 2.

Example of hierarchical classification of genetic systems.

Level of genetic organization Relevant population Examples Conservation Effects Refs
Standard genetic code Most organic life on earth Rules by which four DNA base letters with 43 = 64 possible three-letter words encode 20 standard amino acids (some words are redundant) Several deviations in natural microbes The nature of the code affects the evolvability of all life on earth Maynard Smith and Szathmáry (1995); Ling et al. (2015)
Basic chromosome structure Domain Multiple linear chromosomes in eukaryotes. One or two circular chromosomes in bacteria. All eukaryotes have multiple linear chromosomes, deviating much in number. Most bacteria have one or two circular chromosomes. A few have linear chromosomes. Multiple linear chromosomes allow vast expansion of regulatory ability of individual genes and modules, increased genome size, and sexual differentiation. One or a few circular chromosomes allow efficient replication. Maynard Smith and Szathmáry (1995)
Core regulatory gene complexes (“kernels”) Kingdom and Phylum Genetic networks controlling multicellular and multinuclear organization. Heart-field specification shared by arthropods and vertebrates. Highly conserved and invariant. Deviation often leads to developmental catastrophe. Determine primary kingdom and phylum-level characters that influence basic organismal structure and interaction with the environment Davidson and Erwin (2006)
Peripheral regulatory genes that affect signal transduction systems Class, Order, Family Wnt, Hedgehog, Notch in animals Flexible deployment, even in related species Determine morphological pattern and size of body parts Davidson and Erwin (2006)
Protein-coding genes under regulatory control Genus, Species Skeletogenic and pigment cell differentiation batteries in animals Labile and undergo continuous renovation Determine functional capabilities of body parts Davidson and Erwin (2006)

Under this scheme, natural selection results in the survival of the optimized alleles within species, and thus the allele is the basic unit of optimization (Table 1). Natural reward, in contrast, results in the success of innovative genetic systems shared by higher taxa. At lower levels of the genetic hierarchy, natural reward may act on gene complexes like core regulatory networks, peripheral regulatory modules, or even particular protein-coding genes shared by phyla, orders, families, genera, or species (Table 2). At broad levels, natural reward may act on more basic genetic systems, like chromosome structures or genetic codes, shared by larger groups (Table 2). Natural reward may also act on a combination of genetic systems at different levels of the genetic hierarchy, for example a regulatory network and protein-coding genes that create a novel trait or function (Benton et al. 2019). Because natural reward can operate on any level of the biological hierarchy, I use population in a broad sense to refer to any group of individuals, characterized by a genetic system that codes for a particular trait or function.

To be able to speak of the “success” of a population of organisms in a way that ties to the notion of absolute progress, I define absolute progress as population expansion. This is a similar definition as that used in economics, which typically equates economic progress with economic expansion, and which views increases of GDP as contributing to economic success (Fig. 1A; Nelson 2008; Aghion and Howitt 2009; Xong and Feng 2019). Applied to a group of living organisms, a large population size increases the chance of speciation and decreases the chance of extinction (Darwin 1859. pp. 126, 489; e.g., Hubbell 2005, p. 129), and so bears on a measure of long-term success.

As a measure of biological success, however, population size is biased toward small organisms. Thus, although we may use population size to compare the success of organisms of similar size, comparisons between organisms of different size requires a different measure. Energy flow and biomass are possible substitutes (Lotka 1922), the latter being easier to measure (Odum 1970, p. 82–83). Looking at the world today, the most successful forms of life, as judged by their biomass, are terrestrial plants, followed by bacteria, fungi, animals, archaea, protists, and viruses (Bar-On et al. 2018).

By defining absolute progress in terms of population increase, we are able to separate the measure of success from the traits that cause success. This is useful because it allows us to focus on what it means to be successful. Wasik and Turner (2013) argued that viruses are the most successful inhabitants of the planet because they are the most numerous, extremely diverse in their genetics and habits, and are extremely adaptable. In contrast, we may say that the large population size of viruses is indicative of their small size and that when we normalize for size in our measure of success by using biomass as a substitute, viruses are only about as successful as annelids or mollusks (0.2 Gt Carbon), but less successful than arthropods (1 Gt carbon; Bar-On et al. 2018). That viruses are about as successful as moderately successful animals suggests that viruses have done well despite being small, and we may hypothesize that this moderate success is caused by their adaptability, or their diversity in genetics and habits.

The advancement of life

Advancement is a sort of second-order absolute progress, conveyed by an increased ability to create or disseminate inventions. How do natural selection and natural reward, acting together, yield advancement? To answer this question, I will give a possible example of advancement, which serves as the basis for hypothetico-deductive reasoning. Particularly, I discuss how mammals replaced large non-avian dinosaurs and marine reptiles.

The initial radiation of dinosaurs and marine reptiles started 240 My (Kelley and Pyenson 2015; Baron et al. 2017). By around 200 My, the mammals had appeared and were beginning to evolve the traits that would contribute to their later diversification and success (Luo 2007; Meredith et al. 2011; Wilson et al. 2012). The prior presence of the dinosaurs and marine reptiles, however, prevented mammals from radiating into terrestrial and marine environments.

The incumbent advantage of dinosaurs and marine reptiles was destroyed 66 My, when vertebrates weighing more than 50 pounds were annihilated (Archibald and Favosky 2004; Kelley and Pyenson 2015), coincident with the Chicxulub asteroid impact (Chiarenza et al. 2020). With the large dinosaurs and marine reptiles gone, terrestrial mammals, mostly placentals, rapidly gained size and radiated over the course of 10 my (Smith et al. 2010). Placental mammals then radiated into marine environments (Slater et al. 2010; Kelley and Pyenson 2015). Mammals then exploited more cold-water habitats (Bardet 1994; Slater et al. 2010), yielding a greater diversity of marine species (Kelley and Pyenson 2015), and humans exploited fossil fuels and other power sources previously not used by life (IEA 2019). Humans also now co-opt one third of terrestrial net primary production on the planet through their use of agriculture (Running 2012), and by tending crops in a way that maximizes yield, humans increase the transfer of digestible plant material to higher levels of the food chain, suggesting a large energy flow (Odum 1970, p. 48).

The replacement of dinosaurs and marine reptiles by mammals may be seen as an advancement for two reasons. First, mammals tapped into new niches and energy sources not previously used by dinosaurs and marine reptiles, suggesting a greater innovative capacity. Second, mammals have novel traits that allow the finding of new resources. At a base level, these traits include extended developmental care for young via placentae and mammae (Darwin 1872; Suzuki 2017; Wooding and Burton 2008), as well as improved intelligence, hearing, dentition, and vision (Luo 2007; Wilson et al. 2012; Archibald and Favosky 2004; Kemp 2006). In humans, these traits and others combined fortuitously, allowing tool building, vocal and written language, and cooperation at a large scale (Wallace 1871; Maynard Smith and Szathmáry 1995; Harari 2011). Most of the success of modern humans, however, paralleled the rise of world GDP during the industrial revolution (Fig. 1A). Therefore, understanding the success of humans, and in turn gaining insight on whether mammals are more advanced than dinosaurs, may depend on understanding the economic systems of humans of the past 300 y (see below).

Randomness of invention

The most important assumption of the theory of natural reward is that the complex inventions produced by natural selection are often random with respect to long-term success. This core assumption allows natural reward to operate as a separate deterministic force. If it were true, on the other hand, that natural selection usually produces complex traits for ultimate effects, then natural reward would be largely redundant. By analogy, if allelic variants originated by mutation only in environments where those mutations were advantageous (Cairns et al. 1988), then mutation pressure would drive the spread of optimized alleles. Natural selection would be redundant in producing genetic optimization and, in seeking the simplest possible theory, natural selection could be ignored (Levit and Olsson 2006). Therefore, it is important to investigate the question of whether natural selection usually produces complex traits for ultimate effects, just as it was once important to investigate whether allelic variants originate by mutation preferentially in environments where those mutations are advantageous (Lenski and Mittler 1993).

What do we know about the origin and success of complex traits? To date, we have a detailed knowledge of the actual steps of evolution over intermediate time scales (103–106 generations) in only one famous example, that of the Lenski Long-Term Evolutionary Experiment (LTEE). A major achievement of the LTEE, coming at generation 44,000 was its detailed depiction of the origin and success of citrate metabolism (Blount et al. 2012; Quandt et al. 2014, 2015; Leon et al. 2018). All 12 replicate populations were exposed to the environmental opportunity of citrate, which was included in the nutrient broth to help the bacteria acquire iron (Blount 2017). If natural selection produces complex traits in response to environmental opportunities, then all 12 populations should have evolved citrate metabolism. However, only one population did. This suggests that natural selection has no foresight, but it could be reconciled with teleology if only a single mutation was necessary for citrate metabolism (Blount 2017, p. 161). In that case, natural selection would be responsible for optimizing to the final goal of citrate metabolism, and the difference between lineages would be explained by the random occurrence of a single rare mutation.

The LTEE showed, however, that the evolution of citrate metabolism relied on six selective steps (Fig. 5). The most important was the selection of the gltA mutation at step 4, which meant that the citT duplication was selectively advantageous during step 5, and that it persisted long enough for strong citrate metabolism to be selectively favored at step 6 (Quandt et al. 2015; Fig. 5). Therefore, it was not that natural selection optimized to a final goal of citrate metabolism, but that natural selection favored particular mutations that were advantageous in the immediate environment and stumbled upon a complex invention. The complex invention facilitated a transient population increase, which protected the population from extinction, and by generation 44,000, the citrate-metabolizing lineage was the only one left (Turner et al. 2015). As Blount (2017), p. 161 put it, “the big reward came only at the end.”

Figure 5.

The sequence of steps leading to citrate metabolism in the LTEE. In the Lenski Long-Term Evolution Experiment (LTEE), the complex innovation of citrate metabolism gradually evolved by natural selection through steps 1–6, and was naturally rewarded in the 7th step for exploiting a new resource zone (see text for references).

A second example comes from a series of computer experiments, inspired by the “genetic art” introduced by Dawkins (1986, 1989). In a series of preliminary investigations, Secretan et al. (2008) encouraged humans to “breed” pictures on a website (www.picbreeder.com). Website visitors were given the option to hand off the fruits of their breeding programs to other website visitors, such that particular “evolutionary branches” might be encouraged to diversify and branch further (Secretan et al. 2008, p. 1763). Through repeated bouts of breeding, a number of complex images appeared (Woolley and Stanley 2011; their Fig. 4; Stanley and Lehmann 2015, p. 27–28).

If it were true that complexity in nature were produced by natural selection optimizing to final goals, then it would be expected that an optimization algorithm would discover the complex images faster than the human breeders. However, an experiment employing an optimization algorithm that favored anything more closely resembling the final objective showed that after 30,000 generations of breeding, in 20 trial runs, optimization failed to breed any of the complex images. In contrast, the human breeders, with no knowledge of the final images, bred the same complex images in less than 100 generations (Woolley and Stanley 2011; their Table 1).

These results show that an optimization algorithm, artificially endowed with teleological foresight, was less likely to find its own complex design objective, than human breeders without foresight. This suggests that natural selection, acting as a blind inventor, is actually more likely to discover innovations than a teleological force. In support of this, Lehman and Stanley (2011) also showed that a novelty-search algorithm, which behaves more like the naïve human breeders, was more likely to “discover” complex behavioral programs that successfully navigate a maze, than an optimization algorithm.

What is the evidence from nature, however, that complex traits evolve randomly with respect to the cause for success? One example is kin recognition used for histocompatibility, which is usually cited as a prime example of kin recognition evolved to direct help to kin (Grafen 1990). However, explicit evolutionary models show that discriminatory help selects against kin recognition (Rousset and Roze 2007). Gilbert (2015) therefore proposed an alternative historical model and found that a five-step sequence of evolutionary steps would explain the evolutionary origin of a complex kin recognition system (Gilbert 2015; Fig. 6).

Figure 6.

The sequence of steps leading to kin recognition in Gilbert’s (2015) model of histocompatibility. Histocompatibility gradually evolved by natural selection through steps 1–5, kin recognition evolving adaptively in the 5th step. Whether kin recognition used for histocompatibility is naturally rewarded in a 6th step is an open question.

In his original analysis, Gilbert (2015) found detailed evidence for his predictions in stolidobranch ascidians (Fig. 7C here). Here, I present evidence that kin recognition also evolved independently in phlebobranch and aplousobranch ascidians (Fig. 7A, B). In these two other cases, there is similar evidence of transitional states predicted by Gilbert’s (2015) model (Fig. 7). This suggests that kin recognition did not evolve for the ultimate apparent goal of directing help to kin, but rather through a series of selective steps that ended with discriminatory rejection being favored for avoiding the immediate expression of conflict between non-kin (Fig. 6, steps 3–5). This model suggests that kin recognition may incidentally restrict the spread of social parasites, which might contribute to the persistence and success of complex social systems (Fig. 6; Buss 1987; Metzger and Goff 2016).

Another example of a complex trait in nature is C4 photosynthesis. Edwards (2019) argued C4 photosynthesis evolved through four distinct steps (her Fig. 7). The first step, an increase of bundle sheath relative to mesophyll cells, must have occurred before the biochemical pathways necessary for C4 photosynthesis. The next step, the origin of C2 photosynthesis, involves a less-efficient C02-concentrating mechanism, the opposite of the final effect (Edwards 2019). Therefore, although C4 photosynthesis evolved some 66 times independently in plants (Sage et al. 2011), the spread of C4 photosynthesis is not evidence of selective pressure to survive in an atmosphere characterized by lower C02.

Figure 7.

Cladogram of ascidians. This figure shows the transitional states predicted by Gilbert’s (2015) historical model (Fig. 6). Cladogram is organized by suborders A Phlebobranchia, B Aplousobranchia, C Stolidobranchia, and the form of histocompatibility (fusion-rejection) behavior employed (see Appendix for methods).

These examples show that complex traits may originate randomly with respect to their causes for success. In some other cases, it would appear that the causes for origin and success are the same, and thus that nature’s inventor is not really blind (e.g., examples like mimicry, camouflage, and camera-like eyes; Dawkins 1996, pp. 138–197; Bergstrom and Dugatkin pp. 89–95; Futuyma 2013, pp. 615–619; Zimmer and Emlen 2013, pp. 311–316; Suzuki 2017). However, just as it is unnecessary that mutation is always random with respect to selection (Dawkins 1996, p. 82), it is unnecessary that invention is always random with respect to reward.

Discussion

In this article, I have briefly summarized a new theory of macroevolution that invokes an alternative deterministic force, natural reward. Crucial to this theory is the assumption that the causes for origin of complex traits may be different from the causes for success, an assumption that I have discussed in the light of recent research. In this discussion, I will compare the theory of natural reward, which includes both natural selection and natural reward as deterministic forces, to a theory that includes natural selection alone as a deterministic force. I will concentrate first on the question of absolute progress, as seen from the lens of Darwin’s theory, and I will then discuss the application of the theory of natural reward to the dissemination of inventions. Finally, I will discuss the problems of the apparent sudden origins of new forms in the fossil record, and the causes for humanity’s recent success.

Evolutionists going back to Darwin (1859) have derived arguments for absolute progress in terms of evolvability. The basic argument is that the long-continued action of natural selection will lead to an increase of evolvability, for example as indicated by an increase of variability or propensity to “diverge in character” (e.g., Darwin 1859, p. 118). In the only figure in "The Origin of Species", Darwin argued that there is an overall increase of variability, because the two initially variable species, A and I, give rise to 14 species after 15,000 generations (a seven-fold advantage), while the other nine non-variable species (B-H, K-L) gave rise to the same number as present at the beginning (no advantage). Darwin’s “evolvability” argument explains increased ability to evolve if indeed, “the tendency to variability is in itself hereditary” (Darwin 1859, p. 118).

The basic limitation of Darwin’s evolvability argument is found in most evolvability arguments since (e.g., Dawkins 1986, 1989; Lloyd and Gould 1993, etc.). The main limitation is that it assumes effective resource limitation (Fig. 2A or 2B). With effective resource limitation, an increased ability to evolve by natural selection results only in greater ability to adapt to the immediate conditions of life, but it does not lead to absolute progress (Fig. 4). The secondary limitation is that Darwin’s evolvability argument focuses only on one trait, variability, which falls into a broader class of traits involved with the origin and dissemination of inventions.

The importance of resource abundance for favoring innovative traits is borne out by computer simulation. Lehman and Stanley (2013) showed that more evolvable genotypes spread in environments where population expansion was possible due to the availability of open niches. This result held even without competition within niches, suggesting a natural reward for evolvability that is separate to natural selection. Likewise, Lehman and Miikkulainen (2015) showed that the periodic opening of new niches by the sort of mass extinctions that Darwin (1859) p. 73, 489 ignored can reward traits that increase the probability of founding new niches.

Evolvability arguments similar to Darwin’s also conflate the cause for origin or maintenance of a trait, with the cause for success. In addressing the problem of why sexual reproduction is widespread (Otto 2009, p. S1; Barton 2009, p. 187), for example, evolutionists typically ask why sexual reproduction originates or is maintained (sensu Maynard Smith 1971). Sexual reproduction may spread widely, however, for reasons that have nothing to do with origin or maintenance. For example, sexual reproduction may spread widely because it facilitates hybridization and introgression, which are a major source of genomic novelty across the domains of life (Arnold 2002; Christin et al. 2012; Soucy et al. 2015; Arnold and Kunte 2017), and contribute to adaptive radiation (Seehausen 2004; Yue et al. 2012; Wasik and Turner 2013); or because it also allows the spread of transposable elements, which are a major source of genomic novelty in eukaryotes (Feschotte 2008; Wagner and Lynch 2010; Chuong et al. 2017) and also contribute to adaptive radiation (Ricci et al. 2018). In other words, sexual reproduction may spread widely because of its transient effects on population increase, which cumulatively have vast impacts on distribution. Hybridization and transposable elements, however, would not explain the selective origin or continual adaptive maintenance of sex, because they have detrimental effects in the short term.

The theory of natural reward also unifies traits involved with inventiveness, or the origin of complex traits, and entrepreneurship, or traits involved with their dissemination. Lehman and Stanley (2013) showed that traits that increase the probability of founding a new niche, which could include dispersal traits, increase in abundance when they contribute to population increase, but they only cause spatial sorting (sensu Shine et al. 2011) when they do not contribute to population increase. Familiar examples of disseminating traits are those involved with dispersal, which disseminate through space. However, traits that disseminate through time are also relevant, and these include hardy cysts, seeds, diapause stages, and stochastic phenotype switching traits (Kussell and Leibler 2005; Evans and Dennehey 2005; Shine et al. 2011). These traits can allow survival through catastrophes and can spread by exploiting novel resource zones following clearance (Harries et al. 1999). Traits involved with entrepreneurship (e.g., dispersal) are unified with traits involved with inventiveness (e.g., those affecting variability), because both are naturally rewarded by their effects on transient population increases.

Other entrepreneurial traits are hereditary systems, like the genetic code, which help disseminate inventions. The existing distribution of genetic codes suggests that all existing variants descended from a single code, which was itself fixed in the deep past (Ling et al. 2015). Usually it is assumed that natural selection optimized the genetic code, and evolutionists search for ways that the code might be optimal (Freeland and Hurst 1998). However, given that 64 three-base-pair “words” (codons) encode 20 amino acids and a punctuation mark, there are 2164 possible codes, meaning that arguments for optimality are almost destined to fail by many orders of magnitude (Zamudio and Jose 2017, p. 2). An alternative approach focuses on the innovative capacity of a common code. Under this perspective, early life forms that happened to specialize on the initially most abundant and useful codes gained access to the largest pools of protein innovations, leading to the fixation of a single code (Vetsigian et al. 2006). Similarly, a main explanation for the fixation of English as the worldwide scientific language is that scientific work in Britain had a major impact early during the scientific revolution of the 17th century, and English was thus an abundant scientific language. Using English then allowed scientists to gain access to the largest pools of scientific innovations (Drubin and Kellog 2012). English, however, may not be an optimal scientific language because it has a clumsy relationship between words and numbers (Dehaene 1997; Gladwell 2008).

Even without optimality, the use of a common code or language represents an advancement compared to having many codes or languages, because it enhances the capacity for further innovation sharing (e.g., as also seen in computer coding; Valverde 2016). Yet, this advancement comes at the cost of having a single language or hereditary system that may not be the best. Likewise, science often advances when new theories are useful enough for guiding new research. Yet this advancement comes at the cost of having a single framework that may not be the best of all possible frameworks in the light of further research. This is why occasional revisions of theoretical frameworks are necessary for continued scientific progress (Kuhn 1967; Thagard 1997).

The theory of natural reward also suggests an explanation for the seeming sudden appearance of new forms in the fossil record (Darwin 1859, p. 302; Wright 1948, p. 537; Gould 2002, p. 755). Particularly, it suggests that transient population increases cause previously rare and undetectable forms to become abundant. For example, at generation 30,000 of the LTEE, the strain with the gltA innovation-enabling mutation was undetectable by the standard methods of detection (sensitive to 1–5% frequency; Quandt et al. 2015). The gltA-mutation-bearing strain then appeared suddenly in the frozen fossil record at generation 33,500, also with the citT and dctA mutations (Quandt et al. 2015; their Fig. 1). Taking the perspective of Darwin (1859), p. 279–311, the inability to find the gltA-bearing strain at generation 30,000 would be taken to suggest that the fossils were lost from that time period (Gould 2002, pp. 755–758). Taking the perspective of Gould (2002), p. 759–760, the apparent population stasis leading up to appearance of the gltA-bearing strain at generation 30,000 would be taken as evidence of stasis (Gould 2002, pp. 796–798), and by implication, saltation. In reality, however, it is not that fossils were lost, nor that saltation happened, but that the gltA-bearing lineage was so rare as to be undetectable, and then suddenly became abundant (Fig. 7). In support of this, the ancestor with the gltA mutation was detected at generation 25,000 before the citT and dctA mutations occurred. At that time, the lineage was actually quite abundant, and it then dwindled until about generation 33, 000 (Quandt et al. 2015; their figure 1).

I now revisit the question of whether there is anything about the economic systems of humans that might account for their recent success (Fig. 1A). I argue that the human invention of economic systems that create an artificial reward for innovation led to this success. The main classes of laws providing an artificial reward for innovation are patent laws, which ensure that authors and inventors are rewarded for their efforts (e.g., Queen Elizabeth I 1565; US Const. art. I, § 8, cl. 8) and contract laws, which ensure that entrepreneurs receive profits for spreading inventions to markets (Aidis et al. 2009, pp. 7, 12). Economies that lacked patent and contract laws typically either collapsed or evolved to imitate those that had them (Schlesinger 1995; Guellec and de la Potterie 2007; Park 2008). Additionally, human economic systems have also invented antitrust laws that limit the incumbent power of monopolies (Sherman Antitrust Act of 1890; Clayton Antitrust Act of 1914). Limiting the incumbent power of monopolies can promote large-scale competitions for new markets that may otherwise require economic depressions to stimulate. The use of antitrust laws therefore favors economic growth (Petersen 2013) without the economic equivalent of mass extinction.

In conclusion, Darwin’s theory of evolution gave two conflicting messages, and acceptance of both messages as correct led to a schizophrenic state of modern evolutionary theory. The abnormal interpretation of reality stems from teleology, which appeals to final causes to explain design in nature and the major trends of evolution. Accepting only one of the Darwinian messages as correct allows us to resolve the Darwinian double bind. Under the extended theory of natural reward, the dual forces of natural selection and natural reward, acting as nature’s blind inventor and blind entrepreneur, led to increased innovativeness with time. Moreover, there is no longer a need to appeal to final causes to explain why life has advanced over the billions of years since its origin. Instead, advancement is explained as an expected outcome of two deterministic evolutionary forces, natural selection and natural reward, acting together without foresight for the future.

Acknowledgements

I thank LE Gilbert, J Lehman, M Prôa, YE Stuart, L Hillström, KO Stanley, S Boyer, CM Gilbert, and an anonymous reviewer for comments. This work was initially motivated by a course taught by ES Vrba and by discussions with LW Buss and his former lab group at Yale University in 1999–2002. I thank JE Strassmann and DC Queller and their former lab group at Rice University for a stimulating intellectual atmosphere from 2008–2011. Special appreciation goes to LE Gilbert, CM Gilbert, JL Martinek, and members of the Brackenridge Field Laboratory and Integrative Biology Department at UT Austin, including RM Plowes, JR Crutchfield, NT Jones, CV Hawkes and MJ Ryan, for their encouragement and support.

References

  • Aidis R, Estrin S, Mickiewicz T (2009) Entrepreneurial entry: Which institutions matter? CEPR discussion paper no. 7278. Centre for Economic Policy Research, London.
  • Barton N, Briggs D, Eisen J, Goldstein D, Patel N (2007) Evolution. Cold Springs Harbor Laboratory Press, Cold Springs Harbor, 833 pp.
  • Benton MJ (1996) On the nonprevalence of competitive replacement in the evolution of tetrapods. In: Jablonski D, Erwin DH, Lipps JH (Eds) Evolutionary Paleobiology. University of Chicago Press, Chicago, 185–210.
  • Bergstrom C, Dugatkin L (2011) Evolution. WW Norton and Company, New York, 786 pp.
  • Bishop JD, Sommerfeldt AD (1999) Not like Botryllus: indiscriminate post-metamorphic fusion in a compound ascidian. Proceedings of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences 266: 241–248. https://doi.org/10.1098/rspb.1999.0628
  • Buss LW (1987) The Evolution of Individuality. Princeton University Press, Princeton, 201 pp.
  • Chiarenza AA, Farnsworth A, Mannion PD, Lunt DJ, Valdes PJ, Morgan JV, Allison PA (2020) Asteroid impact, not volcanism, caused the end-Cretaceous dinosaur extinction. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the USA. https://doi.org/10.1073/pnas.2006087117
  • Chuong EB, Elde NC, Feschotte C (2017) Regulatory activities of transposable elements: from conflicts to benefits. Nature Reviews Genetics 18(2): 71–86. https://doi.org/10.1038/nrg.2016.139
  • Christensen C (1997) The Innovator’s Dilemma. Harvard Business Review Press, Cambridge, 288 pp.
  • Darwin CR (1859) On the Origin of Species. John Murray, London, 502 pp.
  • Darwin CR (1872) The Origin of Species (6th ed.). John Murray, London, 460 pp.
  • Darwin CR, Hooker J (1844) 11 Jan. Darwin Correspondence Project, Letter No. 729.
  • Davidson EH, Erwin DH (2006) Gene regulatory networks and the evolution of animal body plans. Science 311(5762): 796–800. https://doi.org/10.1038/nrg2499
  • Dawkins R (1986) The Blind Watchmaker. WW Norton & Company, 491 pp.
  • Dawkins R (1989) The evolution of evolvability. In: Langton CG (Ed.) Artificial Life, MIT Press, Cambridge, 201–220.
  • Dawkins R (1996) Climbing Mount Improbable. WW Norton & Company, New York.
  • Dehaene S (1997) The Number Sense: How the Mind Creates Mathematics. Oxford University Press, Oxford, 352 pp.
  • Dobzhansky T (1951) Genetics and The Origin of Species (3rd Ed.). Columbia University Press, New York, 358 pp.
  • Drubin DG, Kellogg DR (2012) English as the universal language of science: opportunities and challenges. Molecular Biology of the Cell 23(8): 1399–1399. https://doi.org/10.1091/mbc.e12-02-0108
  • Edwards EJ, Osborne CP, Strömberg CA, Smith SA, C4 Grasses Consortium (2010) The origins of C4 grasslands: integrating evolutionary and ecosystem science. Science 328(5978): 587–591. https://doi.org/10.1126/science.1177216
  • Edwards EJ (2019) Evolutionary trajectories, accessibility and other metaphors: the case of C4 and CAM photosynthesis. New Phytologist 223(4): 1742–1755. https://doi.org/10.1111/nph.15851
  • Evans MEK, Dennehy JJ (2005) Germ banking: bet-hedging and variable release from egg and seed dormancy. Quarterly Review of Biology 80(4): 431–451. https://doi.org/10.1086/498282
  • Feschotte C (2008) Transposable elements and the evolution of regulatory networks. Nature Reviews Genetics 9(5): 397–405. https://doi.org/10.1038/nrg2337
  • Felin T, Kauffman S, Koppl R, Longo G (2014) Economic opportunity and evolution: Beyond landscapes and bounded rationality. Strategic Entrepreneurship Journal 8(4): 269–282. https://doi.org/10.1002/sej.1184
  • Fiegna F, Velicer GJ (2003) Competitive fates of bacterial social parasites: persistence and self-induced extinction of Myxococcus xanthus cheaters. Proceedings of the Royal Society of London Series B: Biological Sciences 270(1523): 1527–1534. https://doi.org/10.1098/rspb.2003.2387
  • Fisher RA (1930) The Genetical Theory of Natural Selection. Oxford University Press, Oxford, 272 pp.
  • Futuyma DJ (2013) Evolution (3rd Ed.). Sinauer Associates, Sunderland, 656 pp.
  • Fletcher DC, Michener CD (1987) Kin Recognition in Animals. John Wiley, New York, 465 pp.
  • Freeman S, Herron J (2007) Evolutionary Analysis (3rd Ed. ) Benjamin Cummings, San Francisco, 816 pp.
  • Gago J, Carriquí M, Nadal M, Clemente-Moreno MJ, Coopman RE, Fernie AR, Flexas J (2020) Photosynthesis optimized across land plant phylogeny. Trends in Plant Science 24(10): 947–958. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.tplants.2019.07.002
  • Ghiselin MT (1994) Darwin’s language may seem teleological, but his thinking is another matter. Biology and Philosophy 9(4): 489–492. https://doi.org/10.1007/BF00850377
  • Gilbert OM, Foster KR, Mehdiabadi NJ, Strassmann JE, Queller DC (2007) High relatedness maintains multicellular cooperation in a social amoeba by controlling cheater mutants. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the USA 104(21): 8913–8917. https://doi.org/10.1073/pnas.0702723104
  • Gilbert OM (2015) Histocompatibility as adaptive response to discriminatory within-organism conflict: a historical model. American Naturalist 185(2): 228–42. https://doi.org/10.1086/679442
  • Gladwell M (2008) Outliers: the Story of Success. Little, Brown and Company, New York, 304 pp.
  • Gould SJ (2002) The Structure of Evolutionary Theory. Belknap Press, Cambridge, 1392 pp.
  • Grossman L (2011) Reinventing the inventor. Time Magazine 178: 56–57.
  • Huneman P (2019) Revisiting darwinian teleology: A case for inclusive fitness as design explanation. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part C: Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences 76: e101188. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.shpsc.2019.101188
  • Huxley TH (1870) Lay Sermons, Addresses, and Reviews. MacMillan, London, 396 pp.
  • Isaacson W (2011) Steve Jobs. Simon and Schuster, New York, 656 pp.
  • Kaushika ND, Mishra A, Rai AK (2018) Solar radiation characteristics. In: Kaushika ND, Mishra A, Rai AK (Eds) Solar Photovoltaics: Technology, System Design, Reliability and Viability. Springer International Publishing, Cham, 15–26. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-72404-1_2
  • Kingsley EA, Briscoe DA, Raftos DA (1989) Correlation of histocompatibility reactions with fusion between conspecifics in the solitary urochordate Styela plicata. Biological Bulletin 176(3): 282–289. https://doi.org/10.2307/1541986
  • Kocot KM, Tassia MG, Halanych KM, Swalla BJ (2018) Phylogenomics offers resolution of major tunicate relationships. Molecular Phylogenetics and Evolution 121: 166–173. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.ympev.2018.01.005
  • Koyama H, Watanabe H (1982) Colony specificity in the ascidian, Perophora sagamiensis. Biological Bulletin 162: 171–181. https://doi.org/10.2307/1540812
  • Koyama H, Watanabe H (1984) Fusibility of related colonies in the colonial ascidian, Perophora. Proceedings of the Japan Academy of Sciences B 60: 195–197. https://doi.org/10.2183/pjab.60.195
  • Kuhn TH (1967) The Structure of Scientific Revolutions: Second Edition. University of Chicago Press, Chicago, 210 pp.
  • Laland KN, Uller T, Feldman MW, Sterelny K, Müller GB, Moczek A, Jablonka E, Odling-Smee J (2015) The extended evolutionary synthesis: its structure, assumptions and predictions. Proceedings of the Royal Society of London B 282(1813): 20151019. https://doi.org/10.1098/rspb.2015.1019
  • Lehman J, Stanley KO (2011) Abandoning objectives: evolution through the search for novelty alone. Evolutionary Computation 119(2): 189–223. https://doi.org/10.1162/EVCO_a_00025
  • Leon D, D’Alton S, Quandt EM, Barrick JE (2018) Innovation in an E. coli evolution experiment is contingent on maintaining adaptive potential until competition subsides. PLoS Genetics 14(4): e1007348. https://doi.org/10.1371/journal.pgen.1007348
  • Levit GS, Olsson L (2006) “Evolution on rails”: mechanisms and levels of orthogenesis. In: Annal of the History and Philosophy of Biology. Universitätsverlag Göttingen 11(11): 99–138.
  • Lidgard S, McKinney FK, Taylor PD (1993) Competition, clade replacement, and a history of cyclostome and cheilostome bryozoan diversity. Paleobiology 19(3): 352–371. https://doi.org/10.1017/S0094837300000324
  • Ling J, O’Donoghue P, Söll D (2015) Genetic code flexibility in microorganisms: novel mechanisms and impact on physiology. Nature Reviews Microbiology 13(11): 707–721. https://doi.org/10.1038/nrmicro3568
  • Malthus (1826) An Essay on the Principle of Population (6th Edn, Vol. 1). John Murray, London, 535 pp.
  • Maynard Smith J, Szathmáry E (1995) The Major Transitions in Evolution. WH Freeman, Oxford, 360 pp.
  • Meredith RW, Janecka JE, Gatesy J, Ryder OA, Fisher CA, Teeling EC, Goodbla A, Eizirik E, Simão TLL, Stadler T, Rabosky DL, Honeycutt RL, Flynn JJ, Ingram CM, Steiner C, Williams TL, Robinson TJ, Burk-Herrick A, Westerman M, Ayoub NA, Springer MS, Murphy WJ (2011) Impacts of the cretaceous terrestrial revolution and kpg extinction on mammal diversification. Science 334: 521–524. https://doi.org/10.1126/science.1211028
  • Mukai H, Watanabe H (1974) On the occurrence of colony specificity in some compound ascidians. Biological Bulletin 147(2): 411–421. https://doi.org/10.2307/1540458
  • Murphy AE (Trans.) (2015) Essay on the Nature of Trade in General by R. Cantillon (1755). Liberty Fund, Inc., Indianapolis, 153 pp.
  • Odenwald S (2017) Counting the stars in the Milky Way. Huffington Post.
  • Odum EP (1970) Fundamentals of Ecology (3rd ed.). Philadelphia, Saunders, 574 pp.
  • Okuyama M, Saito Y (2001) Studies on the structure of the brooding organs of two botryllid ascidians, Botryllus delicatus and Botryllus sexiens. Zoological Science 18(3): 397–404. https://doi.org/10.2108/zsj.18.397
  • Paley SJ (2010) The Art of Invention. Prometheus Books, Amherst, 236 pp.
  • Prinsep CR, Biddle CC (Trans.) (1880) JB Say: A Treatise on Political Economy 5th Ed. of 1826. Reprinted 1971. Augusts M. Kelley Publishers, New York, 488 pp.
  • Quandt EM, Deatherage DE, Ellington AD, Georgiou G, Barrick JE (2014) Recursive genomewide recombination and sequencing reveals a key refinement step in the evolution of a metabolic innovation in Escherichia coli. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the USA 111(6): 2217–2222. https://doi.org/10.1073/pnas.1314561111
  • Quandt EM, Gollihar J, Blount ZD, Ellington AD, Georgiou G, Barrick JE (2015) Fine-tuning citrate synthase flux potentiates and refines metabolic innovation in the Lenski evolution experiment. Elife 4: e09696. https://doi.org/10.7554/eLife.09696
  • Queen Elizabeth I (1565) 3. Calendar of Patent Rolls 7 Eliz. 1: 1–331.
  • Ricci M, Peona V, Guichard E, Taccioli C, Boattini A (2018) Transposable elements activity is positively related to rate of speciation in mammals. Journal of Molecular Evolution 86(5): 303–310. https://doi.org/10.1007/s00239-018-9850-z
  • Ruse M (1996) Monad to Man. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, 648 pp.
  • Saito Y, Shirae M, Okuyama M, Cohen S (2001) Phylogeny of Botryllid ascidians. In: Sawada H, Yokosawa H, Lambert CC (Eds) The Biology of Ascidians. Springer Japan, 315–320. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-4-431-66982-1_50
  • Saito Y, Watanabe H (1982) Colony specificity in the compound ascidian, Botryllus scalaris. Proceedings of the Japan Academy of Sciences B 58(4): 105–108. https://doi.org/10.2183/pjab.58.105
  • Schlesinger MN (1995) A sleeping giant awakens: the development of intellectual property law in China. Journal of Chinese Law 9: 93–140.
  • Schmidt GH (1982) Aggregation and fusion between conspecifics of a solitary ascidian. Biological Bulletin 162(2): 195–201. [1982] https://doi.org/10.2307/1540814
  • Secretan J, Beato N, D’Ambrosio DB, Rodriguez A, Campbell A, Stanley KO (2008) Picbreeder: evolving pictures collaboratively online. Proceedings of the SIGCHI Conference on Human Factors in Computing Systems, Florence (Italy), April 2008. Association for Computing Machinery, New York, 1759–1768. https://doi.org/10.1145/1357054.1357328
  • Shine R, Brown GP, Phillips BL (2011) An evolutionary process that assembles phenotypes through space rather than through time. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the USA 108(14): 5708–5711. https://doi.org/10.1073/pnas.1018989108
  • Sigman DM, Hain MP (2012) The biological productivity of the ocean. Nature Education Knowledge 3(6): 1–16.
  • Simpson GG (1944) Tempo and Mode in Evolution. Columbia University Press, New York, 227 pp.
  • Simpson GG (1949) The Meaning of Evolution. Yale University Press, New Haven, 364 pp.
  • Slater GJ, Price SA, Santini F, Alfaro ME (2010) Diversity versus disparity and the radiation of modern cetaceans. Proceedings of the Royal Society of London B 277: 3097–104. https://doi.org/10.1098/rspb.2010.0408
  • Smith FA, Boyer AG, Brown JH, Costa DP, Dayan T, Ernest SKM, Evans AR, Fortelius M, Gittleman JL, Hamilton MJ, Harding LA, Lintulaakso K, Lyons SK, McCain C, Okie JG, Saarinen JJ, Sibly RM, Stephens PR, Theodor J, Uhen MD (2010) The evolution of maximum body size of terrestrial mammals. Science 330: 1216–1219. https://doi.org/10.1126/science.1194830
  • Soucy SM, Huang J, Gogarten JP (2015) Horizontal gene transfer: building the web of life. Nature Reviews Genetics 16(8): 472–482. https://doi.org/10.1038/nrg3962
  • Stauffer RC (1975) Charles Darwin’s Natural Selection. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 692 pp.
  • Staubwasser M, Drăgușin V, Onac BP, Assonov S, Ersek V, Hoffmann DL, Veres D (2018) Impact of climate change on the transition of Neanderthals to modern humans in Europe. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the USA 115(37): 9116–9121. https://doi.org/10.1073/pnas.1808647115
  • Steger U, Achterberg W, Blok K, Bode H, Frenz W, Gather C, Hanekamp G, Imboden D, Jahnke M, Kost M, Kurz R, Nutzinger HG, Ziesemer T (2005) Sustainable Development and Innovation in the Energy Sector Springer, 264 pp.
  • Suzuki TK (2017) On the origin of complex adaptive traits: progress since the Darwin versus Mivart debate. Journal of Experimental Zoology Part B: Molecular and Developmental Evolution 328(4): 304–320. https://doi.org/10.1002/jez.b.22740
  • Svensson EI, Connallon T (2019) How frequency-dependent selection affects population fitness, maladaptation and evolutionary rescue. Evolutionary Applications 12: 1243–1258. https://doi.org/10.1111/eva.12714
  • Tax S, Callender C [Eds] (1960) Evolution after Darwin (Vol. III): Issues in Evolution. University of Chicago Press, Chicago.
  • The Clayton Antitrust (1914) The Clayton Antitrust Act of 1914, 15 U.S.C. §§ 12–27, 29 U.S.C. §§ 52–53.
  • The Sherman Antitrust (1890) The Sherman Antitrust Act of 1890, 26 U.S.C. §§ 1–7.
  • Turner CB, Blount ZD, Lenski RE (2015) Replaying evolution to test the cause of extinction of one ecotype in an experimentally evolved population. PLoS ONE 10(11): e0142050. https://doi.org/10.1371/journal.pone.0142050
  • Valverde S (2016) Major transitions in information technology. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences 371(1701): 20150450. https://doi.org/10.1098/rstb.2015.0450
  • Vetsigian K, Woese C, Goldenfeld N (2006) Collective evolution and the genetic code. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the USA 103(28): 10696–10701. https://doi.org/10.1073/pnas.0603780103
  • Wagner A, Rosen W (2014) Spaces of the possible: universal Darwinism and the wall between technological and biological innovation. Journal of the Royal Society Interface 11(97): e20131190. https://doi.org/10.1098/rsif.2013.1190
  • Wald L (2009) Solar radiation energy (fundamentals). In: Blanco J, Malato S (Eds) Encyclopedia of Life Support System (EOLSS), Eolss Publishers, Oxford, 44–99.
  • Wallace AR (1871) Contributions to the Theory of Natural Selection. MacMillan and Co., London, 384 pp.
  • Wilson GP, Evans AR, Corfe IJ, Smits PD, Fortelius M, Jernvall J (2012) Adaptive radiation of multituberculate mammals before the extinction of dinosaurs. Nature 483: 457–460. https://doi.org/10.1038/nature10880
  • Woolley BG, Stanley K O (2011) On the deleterious effects of a priori objectives on evolution and representation. Proceedings of the 13th annual conference on Genetic and Evolutionary Computation, Dublin (Ireland), July 2011. Association for Computing Machinery, New York, 957–964. https://doi.org/10.1145/2001576.2001707
  • Wozniak S (2007) iWoz. WW Norton, New York, 330 pp.
  • Wright S (1948) Evolution, organic. Encyclopedia Britannica: 524–538.
  • Yue J, Hu X, Sun H, Yang Y, Huang J (2012) Widespread impact of horizontal gene transfer on plant colonization of land. Nature Communications 3(1152): e1152. https://doi.org/10.1038/ncomms2148
  • Yokobori S, Kurabayashi A, Neilan BA, Maruyama T, Hirose E (2006) Multiple origins of the ascidian Prochloron symbiosis: Molecular phylogeny of photosymbiotic and non-symbiotic colonial ascidians inferred from 18S rDNA sequences. Molecular Phylogenetics and Evolution (40): 8–19. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.ympev.2005.11.025
  • Zeng L, Jacobs MW, Swalla BJ (2006) Coloniality has evolved once in Stolidobranch ascidians. Integrative and Comparative Biology 46(3): 255–268. https://doi.org/10.1093/icb/icj035
  • Zimmer C, Emlen DJ (2013) Evolution: Making Sense of Life. Roberts and Company Publishers, 720 pp.

Appendix 1

The species in Fig. 7, listed from top to bottom, are Ciona intestinalis, Perophora orientalis, Perophora sagamiensis, Perophora japonica, Aplidium yamazii, Polycitor proliferus, Diplosoma listeranium, Diplosoma moseleyi, Molgula manhattensis, Molgula complanata, Halocynthai roretzi, Styela plicata, Botryllus scalaris, Botryllus delicatus, Botryllus sexiens, Botryllus schlosseri, and Botrylloides violaceous. I establish character states as follows. To establish whether fusion is at the multicellular or colonial level, I ask whether fusion involves blood vessel fusion or only tunic fusion, respectively (Bishop et al. 1999). Both stolidobranch and phlebobranch ascidians independently evolved coloniality, colony vascular systems, and fusion that can lead to exchange of blood cells (Bishop et al. 1999). In contrast, aplousobranch ascidians independently evolved coloniality without colony vascular systems, where fusion may lead to use of a common tunic but not exchange of blood cells (Bishop et al. 1999). I distinguish the latter situation as colonial fusion, because it involves fusion of colonies but not multicellular individuals. I infer minor histocompatibility by the finding that rejection occurs after considerable fusion. I infer major histocompatibility by the finding that rejection occurs very quickly after first contact (sensu Gilbert 2015).

I establish phylogenetic relationships as follows. Kocot et al. (2018) found that Stolidobranchia are sister to Phlebobranchia+Aplousobranchia. For Phlebobranchia, I assume Perophora sp. have a more recent common ancestor than they do with Ciona intestinalis. For aplousobranch ascidians, I cite Yokobori et al. (2006) for the relationship between Didemnidae (including Didemnum sp. and Diplosoma sp.) and Polycitoridae (including Polycitor proliferus) and Polyclinidae (including Aplidium yamazii). For stolidobranch ascidians, Kocot et al. (2018) and Zeng et al. (2006) showed that Styela plicata and botryllids have a more recent common ancestor with each other than with Halocynthai roretzi and Molgula sp. They also showed that Molgula sp. is sister to the others. Molecular and morphological data indicate Botryllus scalaris is the most basal botryllid (Cohen et al. 1998; Saito et al. 2001). I follow Saito et al. (2001) in assuming Botryllus delicatus and Botryllus sexiens are sister to B. schlosseri and Botrylloides violaceus, and Cohen et al. (1998) for the other botryllid relationships.

For character states, I assume that Ciona intestinalis and Perophora orientalis do not fuse (Cohen et al. 1998), because there are no reports of fusion in C. intestinalis and P. orientalis will not fuse on growing edges (Saito et al. 1994). I also assume that Perophora sagamiensis has minor histocompatibility, while Perophora japonica has major histocompatibility, because P. sagamiensis most often presented delayed rejection and P. japonica rejects immediately (Koyama and Watanabe 1984). I classify P. proliferus as not fusing because, similar to P. orientalis, they do not fuse upon contact (Bishop et al. 1999). I classify Diplosoma listeranium as having indiscriminate colonial-level fusion because they always fuse tunics but not blood vessels (Bishop et al. 1999). I classify A. yamazii and D. moseleyi as having colonial histocompatibility because they fuse tunics and discriminately reject, but do not fuse blood vessels (Bishop et al. 1999). I classify D. moseleyi as having major histocompatibility because the colonies fuse blood vessels during fusion events, but reject immediately before or immediately after initial fusion (Mukai and Watanabe 1974).

I classify Molgula manhattensis, Halocynthai roretzi, and Styela plicata as not fusing because there is little evidence these species fuse in nature. Styela plicata fuses at a frequency of 6.4 X 10-4, and fusion does not lead to systemic chimerism (Kingsley et al. 1989). I classify Molgula complanata as having “indiscriminate fusion,” similar to D. listeranium, because M. complanata fuses, but does not reject (Schmidt 1982). I classify B. scalaris and B. delicatus as having minor histocompatibility because they reject only after blood vessel fusion (Saito et al. 2001; Saito and Watanabe 1982; Okuyama and Saito 2001). I classify B. schlosseri and B. violaceous as having major histocompatibility because both reject prior to blood vessel fusion (Saito et al. 1994; Cohen et al. 1998).

login to comment